MindMap Gallery Introduction to Systematic Thinking-Compiled Edition
Table of contents and excerpts of key contents of "Introduction to Systematic Thinking". "Introduction to Systematic Thinking" is an authoritative guide that comprehensively introduces general systems thinking. It is a masterpiece worth reading in terms of theoretical depth, practical guidance, and broad applicability.
Edited at 2024-04-06 05:45:49One Hundred Years of Solitude is the masterpiece of Gabriel Garcia Marquez. Reading this book begins with making sense of the characters' relationships, which are centered on the Buendía family and tells the story of the family's prosperity and decline, internal relationships and political struggles, self-mixing and rebirth over the course of a hundred years.
One Hundred Years of Solitude is the masterpiece of Gabriel Garcia Marquez. Reading this book begins with making sense of the characters' relationships, which are centered on the Buendía family and tells the story of the family's prosperity and decline, internal relationships and political struggles, self-mixing and rebirth over the course of a hundred years.
Project management is the process of applying specialized knowledge, skills, tools, and methods to project activities so that the project can achieve or exceed the set needs and expectations within the constraints of limited resources. This diagram provides a comprehensive overview of the 8 components of the project management process and can be used as a generic template for direct application.
One Hundred Years of Solitude is the masterpiece of Gabriel Garcia Marquez. Reading this book begins with making sense of the characters' relationships, which are centered on the Buendía family and tells the story of the family's prosperity and decline, internal relationships and political struggles, self-mixing and rebirth over the course of a hundred years.
One Hundred Years of Solitude is the masterpiece of Gabriel Garcia Marquez. Reading this book begins with making sense of the characters' relationships, which are centered on the Buendía family and tells the story of the family's prosperity and decline, internal relationships and political struggles, self-mixing and rebirth over the course of a hundred years.
Project management is the process of applying specialized knowledge, skills, tools, and methods to project activities so that the project can achieve or exceed the set needs and expectations within the constraints of limited resources. This diagram provides a comprehensive overview of the 8 components of the project management process and can be used as a generic template for direct application.
Introduction to Systematic Thinking
Beginning
Preface
Therefore, my responsibility is to collect a large amount of material and organize it into the form of an introduction. I have tried to collect the insights of general systems theorists and subject experts, arrange them in a consistent and helpful order, and translate them into simpler general language so that they can be understood by the general reader.
To solve the important problems we face, we cannot stay at the level of thinking that created them in the first place. ——Einstein
From the outside, the system has behavior. From the inside, the system has structure. The system is the unity of behavior and structure.
How to use this book
For personal use, the best approach may be to read from cover to cover and ignore all literature. The questions at the end of each chapter should be read as part of the text in order to understand the scope of problems to which the chapter content may apply. If a question or quote particularly interests you, take some notes and use the references to research further.
For classroom use, there are several options. For a typical college course, the 7-chapter content can be roughly studied one chapter every other week, with the week of no classes being used for recommended reading.
We are surrounded by various elephant-like systems: physical systems, biological systems, sociological systems, economic systems... These systems are composed of various parts, and the whole is beyond people's observation ability and beyond the brain's ability. Imagination and numeracy. We do not have any a priori knowledge and cannot understand the system as a whole. But driven by great curiosity, we went in groups, one after another, to perceive the components of these systems, and then adopted simplified approximations.
We can only hope to estimate how the computational effort will grow as the size of the problem grows. Experience shows that unless some simplification can be made, the increase in the number of calculations is at least the square of the increase in the number of equations. This is the "square law of calculation".
First consider the most common equation describing the system of two objects. We must first describe the behavior of each object by itself, that is, its "isolated" behavior. We must also consider how the behaviors of the two affect each other, that is, "interact". Finally, we must consider the behavior of the system when neither object is present, the "field" equation.
As the number of objects in the system increases, there is still only 1 "field" equation, and each object requires 1 "isolated" equation to describe its behavior, but the number of "interaction" equations increases rapidly, with n objects requiring 2 ^n interaction equations!
People always simplify complex mechanical systems through informal methods before starting to apply formal methods.
Physics is not dedicated to explaining nature. In fact, the great success of physics stems from its limited goal of revealing the laws of how objects behave. Putting aside the grand goal above and defining a specific scope to explain the phenomenon, this is obviously what we must do now. In fact, specifying the scope of explanation may be the most remarkable discovery in physics so far.
To understand science from a general systems perspective, we should look at physics, especially mechanics, because other sciences often use these sciences as standards.
If there are too many parts, a physicist might be able to write equations that describe the behavior of the different parts, but they won't be able to solve them, even using approximate methods. Yes, the emergence of high-speed computers has expanded the scope of approximate solutions to mechanical systems, but the progress is not significant.
Chapter 1 Problem
1.1 Complexity of the world
It is not the unknown that causes trouble, but the things we think we know but actually do not. ——Will Rogers
The first step in gaining knowledge is admitting ignorance. We know too little about the world, and most people are unwilling to admit it. Yet we must admit it, because the evidence of our ignorance is accumulating on a scale too great to ignore.
Physicists tell us how to control nuclear power, chemists tell us how to increase food production, and geneticists tell us how to improve the quality of fertility. However, science and engineering failed to deal with the secondary effects of primary success.
1.2 Mechanism and mechanical mechanics
1.3 The Square Law of Calculation
1.4 Scientific simplification and simplified science
But the average systems thinker does, because their chosen task is to understand the simplifying assumptions of science. In Wigner's words, these "objects of interest" and "well-defined conditions" limit the scope of science's application and enhance its predictive power. Systems thinkers generally hope to start from the starting point of the process of scientists modeling the world and continue this process to eventually obtain useful models for other sciences.
Newton's research went even further. He noticed that because of the Sun's unique mass, each planet and Sun could be viewed as a system, separate from other systems. In this separated system, only two objects remain. The technique of decomposing a system into several non-interacting subsystems is very important for all mature disciplines, and is certainly equally important for system theorists. To understand the importance of this decomposition, just think of the "square law of calculation."
Among these simplifications, Newton and his contemporaries were generally more aware of and more concerned about simplifying assumptions. Physics professors who teach Newtonian calculations today do not. Therefore, it is difficult for today's students to understand why Newton's calculations of planetary orbits rank among mankind's greatest achievements.
Newton was a genius, not because his brain had super computing power, but because he could simplify and idealize so that ordinary people's brains could understand the world to a certain extent. By studying simplified methods of past successes and failures, we hope that the progress of human knowledge will not rely too much on genius.
1.5 Statistical mechanics and the law of large numbers
Because there are very few average features, this simplification immediately reduces the amount of calculations. Moreover, the prediction accuracy of these average values is very high because the number of molecules is extremely large and satisfies the so-called "law of large numbers." The law of large numbers actually says: The larger the number of observed samples, the closer the observed values are to the predicted average.
These physicists include Gibbs, Boltzmann and Maxwell. They inherited a set of observational laws (such as Wave-Eyer's law) that describe the behavior of gases with certain measurable properties (such as pressure, temperature, and volume). They believed that gases were made of molecules, but needed to explain how this belief related to the observed properties of gases. What they do is to assume that these interesting observed properties are some average properties of molecules, rather than properties of one of the molecules.
We see again that in order to obtain relatively accurate laws about the interaction within an organism and with the external environment, we must require that the organism has a considerable structure and quantity. Otherwise, the number of interacting particles will be too small, and the "law" will be very inaccurate.
What is the scope of application of statistical methods? What is its relationship with the scope of application of mechanical mechanics? There is a saying that statistical mechanics faces "disordered complexity", that is, the system itself is very complex, but its behavior shows enough randomness, and therefore has enough regularity to allow statistical research.
1.6 Law of Means
For the median system, we can expect that it will have more or less large fluctuations, irregularities or deviations from any theory. The importance of the law of middle numbers lies not in its predictive power but in its scope of application. There are actually very few good mechanical systems and statistical systems. What surrounds us is actually middle number systems.
In today's society, mechanical technology benefits from the inspiration of mechanical mechanics, reducing complexity by reducing interrelated components. On the other hand, management techniques benefit from the achievements of statistical mechanics, which regard the crowd as merely interchangeable units in an unstructured group and simplify it by taking the average.
For systems between small numbers and large numbers, both classic methods have fatal flaws. On the one hand, the square law of calculation points out that middle number systems cannot be solved analytically; on the other hand, the square root law of N warns us not to expect too much from the average value.
Like most laws of general systems, we also find a form of the law of numbers in folklore. Converted into our daily experience (we are both familiar with such systems and helpless with their performance), the law of middle numbers becomes Murphy's law: Whatever can happen, will happen.
When analyzing the parts or characteristics of things, we tend to exaggerate the obvious independence and ignore (at least for a period of time) the essential integrity and individuality of the combination. We decompose the body into organs and the skeleton into bones. Psychology is taught in a similar way, subjectively breaking down the mind into its component parts, but we know very well that judgment or knowledge, courage or tenderness, love or fear do not exist independently but are part of the most complex whole. a performance or imaginary coefficient.
Biology and social sciences are not as "successful" as physics. They cannot arbitrarily cut the world in front of them into small pieces, because what they get is indivisible. Anatomists have had some success, but we're not interested in what someone does when they're broken down. Sociologists have had even less success, because their main interest is in "humanity" with the properties of a numerical system, properties that cease to exist if the system is decomposed, abstracted, or averaged. If behavioral scientists try to understand "individuals" through averaging, the individual's characteristics will be spread out. If they try to isolate individuals for research, they also cut off the connection between the research object and other people or other parts of the world. The individual becomes only an artifact of the laboratory and no longer a human being.
Chapter 2 Method
2.1 Organism, analogy and vitalism
Any model uses one thing we think we already know to represent another thing we think we want to know. The process of reasoning may have hundreds of steps of logic, or it may be just an analogy, but in the end we will always get some primitives that we think do not need to study further. For science to have the "ability" to explain, these primitives cannot be too big or too small.
In other words, science is essentially about simplification. However, it must be pointed out that reductionists have not yet succeeded in reducing all phenomena to physical and chemical primitives. Whether they can succeed or not is a purely philosophical question, not a scientific question.
Mechanists claim that all phenomena can be reduced to physical primitives or physical and chemical primitives. They don't really show this for "all phenomena", they just say it.
Some organic theorists pointed out tit for tat that not all phenomena can be reduced to these primitives, because the analysis of living systems must stop at some so-called "life force" or "vital element". "Vital elements" are essentially no more mysterious than "quality", but organic theorists attribute everything they don't understand to vital elements. white. This means that vitality does not actually explain any phenomena, because, like God, it explains them all.
If something can explain everything, it means it can explain nothing. At least, this is the scientific view, and this is why organicism is at odds with scientists.
Organic thinking, on the other hand, relies on analogy, a method used by every physicist before and after Newton. Every important thinker in the history of science has relied on useful analogies to simplify certain steps in thinking.
If the actual situation requires us to move forward, we must not stop at a simple and crude analogy, but polish it into a model that is precise, clear, and predictive.
2.2 Scientists and their classification
If you want to be an excellent generalist, you should not have faith in anything. Russell pointed out that belief is belief in something without any evidence. Any restrictions in beliefs will hinder the freedom of thinking, thereby preventing generalists from traveling freely between various disciplines.
To become a "participant-observer", you must first become a participant, which requires at least learning some local language. In fact, it mainly involves learning various non-verbal communication methods. Similarly, to integrate into a certain work subculture, you first need to learn the way of thinking and communication of this subculture.
People working together develop subcultures in which conceptual patterns can also be found. Groups adopt a common set of standard thought types (usually expressed as specialized words and phrases), thereby simplifying the internal communication process. But the paradox is that the more effective these types of internal communication thinking are, the more difficult it will be to communicate with the outside world.
Paradoxically, some scientists have achieved success in different fields, but this is not because they changed their personal thinking patterns, but because they moved their thinking patterns unchanged from one field to another.
New scientific truth often wins not because it convinces its opponents to see the light, but because its opponents eventually die and a new generation of people who are familiar with the new truth gradually grows up.
Due to the importance of thinking type systems in social groups, outsiders with "better" systems may not necessarily become leaders. Only insiders who fully master the internal system will win.
In his book Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn began to study how new modes of thinking replace old ones, how modes of thinking are passed down from generation to generation, and how modes of thinking promote and hinder scientific progress.
If the observation of thinking types and patterns is extended to the field of science, then "scientific leaders" are those who are least likely to achieve scientific breakthroughs.
The most dangerous mistake when developing a system of thought types is to assume that one thought pattern is more "real" than another.
One manifestation of national superiority is the belief that one's own culture is "superior" to those cultures that one does not understand.
Some scientists can also manage to fit into the thinking patterns of several disciplines. How did they do it? Whenever asked about this, they expressed their belief that there is an inherent unity in science. They also have only one mode of thinking, but their starting point is very high. People with this thinking mode believe that thinking modes in different fields are very similar, although their expression forms are often different.
The power of reasoning does not lie in how reasoning uses rules to guide our imagination, but in liberating us from the constraints of experience and traditional rules.
2.3 The Purpose of General System Beliefs
In a sense, the first-order sequence is the basis of the second-order sequence, and the main method for discovering the laws of general systems is induction. Generally, system researchers start from the laws of different disciplines, look for similarities among them, and then announce new "laws about laws" to the world. The general rules in various disciplines are just special cases.
The power of generalization through induction is that we can use general rules to draw certain conclusions about unobserved situations. This is also the reason why generals can transfer from one subject to another. Every success will increase people's trust in the second-order sequence.
Of course, faith is necessary, because not every jump between disciplines can be successful. Why? Because induction cannot always be effective. But why aren't we more cautious? Why not wait for more evidence? The reason is that knowledge is growing explosively, and our brains are limited by the square law of calculation.
A general systems approach will appeal to those who are impatient to wait for a precise approach, but mere impatience is not enough. To become an excellent generalist, you must learn to ignore the data and only see the "big picture" of things.
To become successful generalists, we must approach complex systems with a naive, simple attitude. We must be like children, because there is good evidence that children understand many complex ideas in this way: first by forming a general impression of the whole, and then by drilling down to specific differences.
A four-year-old child who does not know letters and musical notes can, after a day or a month of observation, easily identify different songs in the book based on the title and the appearance of the page. To them, each page in the book represents a particular pattern, but to us, each page has a similar form because we see each word or each letter.
2.4 The nature of general system laws
In fact, we can extract a new general system law: If a fact conflicts with a law, then refuse to accept the fact or change the definition, but never abandon the law. This can be called the law of law protection.
But it's like the eternal paradox that teachers face: teach facts and charts, or teach truth. To teach a model, the teacher must use concrete diagrams and clearly illustrate something that cannot be seen at all. Students must "learn" something so that they later realize that it is not quite what they learned it to be. But by that time, he had grasped the essence of things and began to get closer to the truth. They will spend their lives constantly revising and getting closer to the truth.
If a law contains many conditions, it can be difficult to remember when to use it, because each condition limits the scope of the law. The fewer conditions there are in a law, the more general it is. Add conditions or change term definitions? When we face such a problem, we usually choose to redefine the term.
The pattern of scientific assertions is "if...then...". We often forget that scientific laws are conditional because they are often stated in a very simple way, that is, by omitting or abbreviating the "what if" part. This part must be omitted because if we were serious enough to write it all out, it would be too long.
We assume that in order to obtain accurate conclusions from general system laws, we must fully examine their inner meaning. Therefore, we do not add various qualifications to the general system laws to make them more accurate, but maintain their original simplicity and make them easier to remember. And, whenever possible, we use meaningful phrases and catchy names that are easy for everyone to remember.
"Category 1" perpetual motion machines
Many general system laws are expressed in a variety of ways: as definitions, as methods of measurement, as exploratory tools, especially in negative forms that are easier to remember.
Now, we see the different roles of laws in scientific thinking. They describe measurement guidelines, define terms in laws, remind us to look for things we have not noticed before, and predict future behavior. They also become something of a focal point around which measurement methods, the meaning of terms, and problem-solving techniques can be discussed.
The law is easier to remember if you can give illustrative examples. We hope to avoid empty generalizations, because only broad generalizations are not enough. "Broad generalizations plus pleasant special cases are the only fruitful concepts."
Any general law must apply to at least two specific situations.
There should be at least two exceptions to any general law.
Law of combination: The whole is greater than the sum of its parts.
The law of decomposition, that is: the part is greater than the part of the whole.
2.5 Types of systems thinking
The main role of models is not so much to explain and predict (although ultimately this is attributed to the main role of science), but rather to focus thinking and ask tough questions. Best of all, it's fun to invent and play with models, and the models have a life of their own. Compared with living things, the principle of "survival of the fittest" is even more suitable for models. However, if there is no real need or real purpose, you should not invent models arbitrarily.
Systems theory (originally an attempt to overcome the current problem of overspecialization) became one of hundreds of academic specialties. Moreover, systems science is centered on computer technology, cybernetics, automation and systems engineering, which seems to make systems thinking become another technology (actually the ultimate technology), making human beings and society more like a "huge machine" "...
The contribution of general systems methods to thinking may be fully reflected in the methods of general systems scholars to deal with new courses.
When general systems scholars encounter laws in a specialized field, they are often able to relate them to the "laws" of general systems that they know. He will identify some special assumptions and convert his general system laws into the laws of economics or other disciplines.
Therefore, the general system method can significantly save thinking time in course learning. This is also true when studying various situations or special systems.
Chapter 3 System and Illusion
The real world gives its subset. The product space represents the observer's uncertainty. If you switch to another observer, the product space may change accordingly. Two observers may adopt different product spaces in which they record the same subset of some real events that occur on real objects. Therefore, a "constraint" is a relationship between an observer and a thing. The properties of any particular constraint depend on both the thing and the observer. Therefore, the basic part of organization theory has to do with some attributes that are not inherent to the object, but are the relationship between the observer and the thing. ——W. Ross Ashby
3.1 A system is a view of the world
Einstein: The belief that the external world exists independently of the perceiving subject forms the basis of all science.
What is the system? Poets all know that a system is a view of the world.
In this way, the system is playing games rather than acquiring knowledge. Knowledge is "truth", knowledge is "facts". If two scientists use different "systems" to observe the same thing, science is not "much better" than poetry. One person will see "chic and civilized", another person will see "sloppy clothes".
That's the "banana principle": heuristic thinking methods don't tell you when to stop.
We forgot about the banana principle and thought we could continue to use this method forever. The more achievements we get, the more convinced we are that our approach is correct. But the more convinced we are, the easier it is to fall into illusion.
Perception reacts exactly the same to reality and illusion, and many perceptions leave us with a deep impression that is essentially unforgettable, even if it is an illusion.
3.2 Absolute thinking and relative thinking
With "man-made" systems we can talk about their "purpose"; with "natural" systems we absolutely cannot.
People can say or write statements that are perfectly acceptable but don't make any sense. If we study some meaningless sentences, we can better understand how to say them meaningfully, because exceptions do not prove the rule, but teach us how to understand the rule.
Certain sentences seem to have absolute meaning because almost everyone agrees that it contains meaning.
Much of people's dissatisfaction with man-made systems stems from a disagreement with the "purpose" of these systems' design: that is, what the system "exactly" is. Of course, the answer is that the system has no "purpose", because "purpose" is a relationship, not something that can "have".
Therefore, what Miller said is not the only reason for the existence of these institutions, but it can more or less represent the official public reason, just like the public's recognition of the meaning of a certain word.
Both sides are right, but because everyone uses absolute statements, there is a problem. It seems that the "emergent" property is some "thing" possessed by the system, rather than a relationship between the system and its observer. These properties "emerge" when observers cannot or do not make correct predictions. We often find examples of things that appear "emergent" to one observer and "predictable" to another.
The system is completely man-made. … If we include a certain relationship in the system or ignore it, we may be doing it right or wrong. But this inclusion does not create truth, nor is ignoring it a fallacy. In this sense, the reasons for the correct steps are entirely pragmatic and depend on the relevance of what is included or ignored to the purpose of the system design.
3.3 System is a collection
In fact, no one can prove that he can choose things arbitrarily. Therefore, if we cannot rule out the influence of conscious arbitrary choices on structure, we will find that the observer is acting in a way that causes unwanted structure to slip into other systems.
overall. In fact, it's hard to find an arbitrary system because once we think of one, it becomes somewhat non-arbitrary.
We are not aware of the selection process taking place in our brains, but even if sometimes we are aware of possible ambiguities, there may still be more problems hiding in the dark places.
Our simplest thinking activities are actually not simple. Although it is not completely rational, it is not completely arbitrary either. Although we can use our brains to carry out thinking activities, we basically don't know how these thinking activities are carried out.
The most popular method of ignoring the observer is to jump directly into the mathematical description of the system (the so-called "mathematical system"), without saying a word about how to choose this description method.
Set mathematics (set theory) explains many properties of sets, but it does not tell us how observers choose sets.
Of all the conceptual schemes for selecting sets, the initial approach was simple, limited enumerations: we faithfully recorded them.
But strictly speaking, the ideal representative element is a concept constructed in the mind of the observer, and it may become an effective way to summarize a large amount of data. However, taxonomists often find that it may just be a tempting detour that leads to the fallacy of decomposition.
In any case, we rarely enumerate all the sets that form the basis of our thinking. The enumeration method forms the conceptual basis for other operations. Although it has its own hazards, it is insignificant compared with the damage that may be caused by the derivation method. The worst possible among these derivation methods is to represent a set by a typical element.
The ellipses at the back represent the process of "and so on". This process follows certain rules. This rule should be easily deduced from the above three examples. Rules, whether implicit or explicit, constitute the third common way of defining sets (the others being enumeration and canonical elements).
But in most cases, explicit rules are only used in mathematical operations, such as selecting even numbers to form a set. In the real world, constructing rules is often too difficult for practical application.
3.4 Observers and Observation Results
There is no right or wrong in mathematical arguments, just as mathematicians say, there are only "reasonable" and "unreasonable". Reasonable, in fact, means internal consistency.
As long as the members of a set are "not nothing," our reasoning is strictly content-independent, that is, it is a purely mathematical description.
In fact, if we can say what they are, we are no longer talking about general systems, but specific systems.
So far, we have deliberately not made it clear what the collection of things that makes up the system is. Hall and Fagan as engineers put it bluntly that they are collections of objects. Other authors speak of a collection of "parts", "elements", "properties", "components" or "variables". This inconsistency means that no one knows what the collection of systems actually is.
Mathematicians generally assume that no matter what connections are made, unsound arguments can never be established.
In other words, the observer can be defined based on the observation results obtained. The set notation allows us to realize that an observer has two meanings: his type of observation, and the range of choices within each type.
The first joyful property of using sets is the refinement of the concept of an observer. What an observer does is observe. These observations may be some kind of feeling from physiological organs, or they may be readings from measuring instruments, or they may be a combination of the two. An observation can be expressed as selecting an element from a set that contains all possible observations of this type by this observer.
In the "observer" model, we must always remind ourselves: How much computing power does this model require? But please note that we do not require that our "observer" can make every observation "correctly" (the ragged and shabby elements), because these are our original, undefined elements, and when using them, "Correct" is meaningless.
The product set may sometimes be too broad a model for the observer, because although the observer can distinguish each element in a single set, it may not be able to obtain all combinations.
Using it, we make combinatorial errors. Using such a model, we might conclude that Herrick could observe phenomena that he actually could not. That is, our model may be too general.
A complete observation by the observer is to make a selection for each set within the observation range. Thus, for Herrick, {girdle, fluttering} is a complete observation, as is {cuffs, neglect}. Because the Outfits collection has 6 elements and the Misfits collection has 8 elements, the result is 6 times 8
3.5 The Law of Irrelevance
The above points can be summarized as independent laws: laws do not depend on the choice of specific symbols.
We may not be able to tell whether an observation is correct. However, without a symbolic representation of "correctness," there cannot be an in-depth discussion of observers and their observations. Therefore, the concept of consistency is introduced here: that is, whether one set of observation results is consistent with another set. Clearly, as Lincoln pointed out, the consistency of symbols does not depend on how the observer names the observation.
"If a dog's tail is called a leg, then how many legs does a dog have?" "Five?" "No, four. Calling a tail a leg does not mean that it becomes a leg."
In order to apply the principle of irrelevance, we usually rely on mathematical symbols to remove burrs from speech. To test whether two observers agree, first normalize their observations.
The question of consistency is easy to answer. If for every symbol in B, there will never be two different symbols corresponding to it in A, then A and B are consistent.
From B to A is a many-to-one mapping, and from A to B is a one-to-many mapping. Since an element in A can be mapped to multiple elements in B, we consider B and A to be inconsistent, even if A and B are consistent at this time.
But for simple cases, by introducing an obviously fictitious "super-observer", we can talk about different perspectives. This super observer does not need to know everything, as long as the observation ability is above other observers.
Chapter 4 Interpretation of Observations
4.1 Status
The game you have been playing is what systems researchers call a "black box." The rules of the "black box" game prohibit observers from looking "inside" the black box and participating in the manipulation. The purpose of playing this concept game is to deepen your understanding of the observation process. The black box can be used both as a conceptual tool and as an effective teaching tool. But it must not be understood as a rigorous model with many actual observers.
Note that the concept of a super-super-observer is much like the concept of "fact" in that it encompasses "all possible" observations. In other words, what we call "fact" is very close to what some people call "God."
In fact, as a super observer, you have no power at all: you know everything but have no power.
Abbreviations are useful for recording the behavior of boxes, because although you have super powers of observation, you do not have super powers of memory.
Queen of Hearts Music Box
Since there are very few ordered pairs, it is easy to write them in the form of a table, representing the mapping from the set of observed states to itself (see Figure 4-2). In the previous chapter, we used this mapping form to illustrate the consistency of the two views. But a map can represent a relationship between any two sets (more precisely, from any set to any other set), including to itself.
Although the three representations in Figure 4-2 are equivalent mathematically, they are not the same psychologically. For example, in a directed graph, we can immediately see that the sequence forms a cycle, while in the other two representations, it is not so obvious.
4.2 Eye-brain law
Therefore, the balance between "eyesight" and "brain power" cannot be too biased in either direction. The scientific problem is to find the right compromise.
As the saying goes, "seeing everything" does not mean "understanding everything", because understanding means knowing which details can be ignored. Our "learning" is just seeing the "same" situation recurring. This is what we call a "state", and if this situation is repeated, the observer can recognize it again.
Because the inventor "kneaded" several of our states into one state, we can map the directed graph in the super observer's perspective to obtain the inventor's perspective. For example, the loop "a n i k" maps to "A B C E". If your perspective cannot surpass the inventor's perspective, we cannot accomplish this mapping in the only way, and the inventor cannot map his perspective to yours.
Although each of your states corresponds to a state of the inventor, the structures you see are different. For example, what you see is a cycle with 10 states, and what he sees is a cycle with only 5 states, that is, "B D F C E" is repeated twice. It's like one academic year for the janitor, but two semesters for the dean.
Distinguishing too many states is what we mentioned earlier as insufficient generalization.
The universal observer's law, that is, the eye-brain law: To a certain extent, brainpower can make up for the lack of observation. Based on symmetry, we can immediately derive the brain-eye law: To a certain extent, observation can make up for the lack of brain power.
An experienced doctor would need far fewer test results to make the same diagnosis. But to a certain extent, an intern doctor can replace a laboratory technician who has been working for many years, even though he has not accumulated much experience.
4.3 Generalized laws of thermodynamics
Science does not deal with miracles, nor can it deal with miracles. Science only deals with repeated events. Every science must have some unique way of combining the states of the systems it observes in order to produce replications.
A distinction is made between original properties and auxiliary properties - the former is intrinsic to matter, and the latter is the product of the interaction between a subject possessing certain original properties and the sensory organs of a human or animal observer.
Likewise, the assumption that observations must be consistent with existing theory introduces conservatism into scientific research. If an observation is inconsistent with existing theory, it is likely to be discarded as an "error."
Of course, it is unscientific to completely replace observation with theory. Worse is the formality of observation, which discards any observation that does not fit the theory as fake.
"A state is a situation that can be recognized when it recurs." But if we do not combine multiple states into one "state", no state will recur. Therefore, in order to learn, we must give up some potential differences in states and give up the possibility of learning all the details. Alternatively, we can write it as the dough-kneading law: If we want to learn something, we must not think about learning everything.
The more common things happen, the more often they occur: 1. Because there is some physical reason that leads to a preference for certain states (first law) or: 2. Because there is some spiritual reason (Second Law)
Let us seemingly cautiously propose a law, the so-called general law of thermodynamics: In the absence of special restrictions, states with a high probability of occurrence are more likely to be observed than states with a low probability of occurrence.
But to statisticians, the likelihood of these two hands appearing is the same. Why? If the cards are dealt fairly, then the probability of occurrence of any precisely set 13-card pattern is the same as the probability of occurrence of another set pattern of cards. In fact, this is what statisticians mean by "fair dealing." This is also consistent with our general system intuition based on irrelevant laws. Do playing cards care what is drawn on them? However, the bridge player's intuition is different. Why do they intuitively believe that the second hand of cards is more realistic than the first hand of cards? The reason is that the rules of the game of bridge are formulated by people and give important meaning to certain combinations of cards, otherwise they are just insignificant combinations. When we learn to play poker, we learn to ignore certain parts that are not important to the game.
In an actual bridge game, the probability of the first hand of cards being seen is even much greater than that of the third hand of cards! Why? Because although the probability of the third hand of cards appearing is high, it will almost never be seen, that is, it will not be particularly noticed by people playing cards.
4.4 Function symbols and simplification ideas
In actual situations, the observer must define the scope and granularity of the observation himself, that is, the breadth and depth. Since these characteristics may play a decisive role in the observation, we cannot just wave our hands and skip this process. When an observer chooses a particular scope of observation, he is actually claiming that what is contained in it is an important feature, or at least the most important thing he can observe. For this situation, there is a simple notation in mathematics called function notation.
Function symbols are particularly important in general system thinking, because when we cannot accurately describe the behavioral characteristics of the system, we can use it to represent part of the knowledge of the system.
Function notation can also be used with explicit formulas to represent an intermediate stage of knowledge between functional dependencies and exact formulas.
Since scientific "explanations" always reduce one phenomenon to the conditions of other phenomena, the representation of functional decomposition is very tempting.
So what mistakes do scientists make when doing this kind of decomposition? There are two main answers to this question. 1. At a certain stage, he may omit something in a functional relationship, and further decomposition will cause errors because of this, although a good approximate law may be obtained. We can call it an incomplete fallacy. 2. Even if the observation is complete, the decomposition process will eventually stop, either because the observer's ability is limited (including the observer's patience is limited), or because the "actual" situation does not allow continued decomposition.
4.5 Incompleteness and Past Completeness
Since the state described by the black box is all the observable things we have observed, there is no way to choose a better observation method to observe this black box based on the observation results themselves. The black box tells us through its behavior that observation is incomplete because the state is not certain. However, it cannot tell us how to refine the observation so that it becomes state-definitive. We can only continue to observe, so inventors and physicists are faced with the problem of how to choose a perspective.
All success in physics research depends on the judicious selection of the most important objects of observation, combined with the brain's spontaneous abstraction of some features. Although these characteristics are attractive, current science is not advanced enough for research to yield useful results.
If we omit something from T = f (a), then further decomposition cannot guarantee logical correctness, and the incompleteness fallacy appears.
To say that a functional relationship is "wrong" means that the "real" equation is not included in the set is possible. Either because T does not depend on a (too complete), or because T also depends on other variables besides a (incomplete). What is the basis for making this conclusion? Obviously, one can only observe the behavior of T and a.
If the observation range can be easily expanded, but the brain's computing power is poor, then we choose: T = f (a, b, c) because this formula is relatively "simple". On the other hand, if we have strong computing power but weak observation ability, then choose: T = f (b, c) in order to think more and observe less. However, as long as we are limited to this set of observations, we cannot judge which statement is "correct". This is the basic rule of the black box game.
For black box observation, once no new observation results appear, it is impossible to solve the problem of isomorphism and cannot make a choice among the collection of models. Without opening the box, we don't know whether it is gears or circuits, or a trained monkey shaking the joystick.
But we may also choose: T = f (a, b, c) because we did not notice: T = f (a, c) can already meet the requirements. Or because we notice it but are not satisfied with the formula; or because we are physicists and know "physical systems don't behave that way"; or because we are psychologists and know "people don't behave that way" behavior"; or because we stubbornly believe that "b must be included no matter what". These choices are arbitrary, which ensures that different observers have many ways to interpret their observations, not only explaining which configuration is chosen, but even explaining "what observations are most important."
If there are two models that fit all the observed data, we say that the two models are isomorphic, that is, they have "the same shape." Mathematically, these two models must fit all possible data.
Which is the "correct" answer? Which one can "explain" the observation? For any finite set of observations, the set of explanations is infinite.
Because we are looking at the problem from the perspective of a super observer, we can let other observers expand the observation, improve the granularity of observation, or enhance the memory ability, but they do not have the information needed to make these choices.
We just saw the failure of the decomposition strategy caused by incompleteness. In fact, we can turn this idea upside down and use it as an intuitive definition of completeness. In other words, no matter how we choose from isomorphisms or how many fine perspectives we decompose into, we will not discover new essences. We also see that completeness can only be an approximation, and since it is based on a jump of inductive belief, it cannot be guaranteed to be correct. The reductionist fallacy arising from incompleteness is acceptable because we have all experienced it in some form.
4.6 Generalized complementarity principle
The general systems view is based on simpler assumptions and is therefore more general. If, for some reason, the observer does not make endless improvements to the observation, then there will be complementarity between any two viewpoints. Because in almost all cases, there is always some reason for us to stop endlessly improving observation methods, so we can remove the conditions and get the general law of complementarity: Any two views are complementary.
However, the second reason for the failure of simplification is more difficult for some people to accept, and this is the issue of complementarity. Physicists first encountered this problem of fit and predictability because physics was more advanced in its ability to apply simplifying strategies. In addition, some scientists (or people who call themselves scientists) are usually so far away from a complete view that they are not surprised that their decompositions sometimes go wrong. If physics had not proposed "complementarity" (a peculiar model of reductionism), then probably no one would have accepted this concept.
However, please note the complementary nature of this approach. In order to accurately measure the speed, we hope that the blurred ghost image will be as long as possible, but at the same time, in order to accurately measure the position, we also require the ghost image to be as short as possible. Therefore, no matter how you choose the shutter speed, the result is a compromise, and different observers will set different shutter speeds and thus see different (or complementary) photos.
Physicists are not lazy: if a convenient experiment leads to complementarity and complementarity can be avoided by adopting a less convenient method, he will give up the convenient method. He would look for higher resolution film, he would abandon the camera and build a radar, he might even ditch the radar and build a laser. They never give up looking for a better way just for the sake of "convenience". Nothing could cause them to give up their quest for the Holy Grail except the "laws of nature", i.e. indivisible physical interaction. No wonder such people do not easily accept complementarity!
The key point of the idea of complementarity is that they are two viewpoints that are not completely independent but are irreducible to each other.
Reduction is just one way to achieve understanding, there are many others. Once we stop looking more closely at a small part of the world and start looking more closely at science itself, we discover that reductionism is an ideal that has never been realized in reality. Reductionism is just a scientific belief. It must be belief, because no one has ever seen the final reduced state of any set of observations.
Chapter 5 Decomposition of Observations
In this chapter we discuss how the limited thinking abilities of observers affect the observations they make.
The conclusion is obviously that if our memory is limited, then decomposing a system into several independent subsystems allows us to better predict the behavior of the system. This is the scientific method. If it were not for the limited capacity of the brain, there would be no need to do this. In fact, the existence of science is the best proof of the limited capabilities of the human brain.
Again, our limited abilities are the fundamental reason why we want our views to be "natural" or "satisfactory", because we cannot have two different views in our minds at all times.
Rules should not rely on a specific symbolic representation. Please note the word "should". The difference between your (R, G, W) and the inventor's (light grid, Mimus) lies in the choice of symbols, because your ability to decompose states is exactly the same.
In most common situations, a "red light" or "tone" is sufficient for system observation. But in this warehouse, if you can learn to "see" bright styles and Mimus, then the world you see will be simple.
Difference Law: A law should not depend on a particular symbolic representation, but the opposite is often true.
5.1 Metaphors of science
In science, as in poetry, the important quality lies not in the completed metaphor itself, but in the process of transformation, that is, the process of making the metaphor. Because of the structure of poetry or science itself, metaphors can be built on other metaphors, and functions can be built on other functions.
How does the handyman know that the upcoming job will be similar to the one in the past? This is just a belief that we have encountered before. Maybe we should name it Empirical axiom: The future will be like the past because in the past, the future will be like the past.
On this level, science and poetry are very similar. The poet begins with a metaphor and then goes on to explain in detail how his lover is like a rose, or how the dawn is like a goddess who can be embraced. The scientist starts with a complete view, then proceeds to revise and simplify, finally reducing the original function to a function of something else. Like the poet, the final reduction is assumed to be known and therefore does not need to be defined.
The specialization of science has brought about a problem, that is, scientists in different fields rarely have common experiences, and therefore lack a basis for communication.
Metaphors can only work if we understand (or think we understand) certain characteristics of one thing and transfer them to another thing.
If a thing in the present can be replaced by another thing in the past, the two things are similar.
Science, like poetry, the meanings of the words we use must ultimately come from observation. "We proceed step by step according to reasoning", but we must start from some property of the loop. Similarly, we can gradually understand the meaning of dawn based on the metaphors of Burns and Rimbaud, but we must first know the meaning of "rose".
Poetry based on other poetry is often called "academic" poetry because the basis of its reference is not the direct experience of the real world, but the experience of other poetry. By the same token, science based on other sciences is often called "academic" science.
5.2 Things and boundaries
The idea of clearly distinguishing different parts is deeply ingrained, so we are confident that we can always distinguish the inside from the outside, even if it may take a lot of effort. By analogy, we apply this concept to all systems, using the word "system" to mean "inside" and "environment" to mean "outside."
We use the metaphor of "part" or "thing", which is closely related to our experience of physical space, especially our experience of "boundaries".
One of the deepest hidden scientific metaphors is the concept of a "thing" or "part" that can be clearly distinguished from other things or parts.
These "things" or "parts" are the owners of "properties" or "properties", they possess these properties, just like a matchbox contains matches or a pig carries fat.
Even so, we encounter difficulties in reasoning when dealing with systems with practical boundaries. Problems often arise because we choose boundaries based on past experience or the experience of our predecessors. Since these experiences are very effective in most cases, when they are invalid, it is difficult for us to get rid of their influence.
The problem here is that the "boundary" may not be infinitely thin, it just happens to belong to both the system and the environment. This kind of boundary is not a division, but a connection.
Therefore, as scientists, if we draw more concrete conclusions about a system, we must describe the segmentation more precisely and not stop at poetic metaphors.
5.3 Properties and immutable laws
But after just a few minutes of observation, we begin to transfer what we learn from one situation to situations we think are similar. One of the benefits of decomposing a system into its properties is that it is possible to extend the view to unobserved states.
For observers with limited memory, properties have a thinking function. We may think that some properties are more "natural" than others, but this simply means that we are more accustomed to observing in that way.
We call this way of pointing to definitions "exemplary definitions." Although we may use another set of properties when explaining one set of properties, we still hide the fact that the original set is obtained through the definition of examples. Indeed, we have moved too far away from the original definition to distinguish between original properties and derived properties.
As our work environment becomes increasingly unfamiliar, those inherited and learned perceptual abilities will become increasingly ineffective.
Invariance law: For any given property, there are some transformations that keep it unchanged and some transformations that change it.
Change can only be understood by observing what remains the same. Permanence can be understood only by observing what transformations occur.
5.4 Split
Obviously, if I cannot always use a specific state to identify a quality or attribute, then it cannot satisfy the properties we define.
If segmentation describes a property, it means that when the state is constant, this property does not change over time.
A relationship must conform to our intuitive understanding of properties, and the second attribute is symmetry.
Even if "friendship" is a symmetrical relationship in a specific system, we still cannot divide this system into "friends" subsystems due to the need for transitivity, that is, the third condition.
Transitivity errors are the most common mistakes made when discussing properties or parts.
5.5 Law of strong connection
Through similar arguments, we will find that as time goes by, systems that are easy to decompose have been decomposed, and the remaining systems are generally closely connected and more difficult to decompose.
Just like scientists or poets, what they pursue is to approach "truth", and this approach can never be completed.
Only by trying to change one factor at a time can we know whether they should be called "factors" or "attributes". According to the law of invariance, it is the transformations we try, the things that preserve or destroy, that tell us the meaning of a particular factor or attribute.
The Law of Perfect Systems: The true properties of a system cannot be studied.
The accumulated problems include two situations. In the first case, the current science can solve it, but it has not yet been solved, either because there is no attempt or because of improper understanding. In the second case, current tools are not enough. This is what the general systems theory movement is really concerned with.
The law of forming strong connections: On average, the tightness of system connections is above the average level.
We do not intend to use this particular form to say outright that a system is a perfect system, but simply to call attention to the interdependent nature of it.
Chapter 6 Description of Behavior
For me, doing operational analysis convinced me, and the more I did it the more convinced I became, that it is better to analyze behavior or what is happening, rather than to study abstract descriptions of objects or static objects.
6.1 Simulation: White Box
As a general simulation tool, digital computers have some practical advantages that scale models and analog computers do not have, but here we only need to pay attention to one advantage, which is "programming". This mechanism allows us to use a more natural language to build a white box system, so that we can stand on the same starting line when discussing.
Some systems theorists view simulation as the ultimate tool because they believe that to explain an understanding of behavior, one must construct a system to exhibit that behavior. The inside of the system is no longer completely hidden, but completely exposed. This is a white box, not a black box.
Among human inventions, digital computers are the easiest to describe functionally. It is indeed very variable, and in its behavior (when it is running normally), the only characteristics that can be detected are almost exclusively those of the organization as a whole.
In previous chapters, we discussed "black boxes": the only way to understand such a system is to observe its behavior.
System modelers must work hard to overcome their own instincts
We can construct a physical model according to a certain proportion to simulate the system. The study of this scaling law is called "dimensional analysis" and is especially recommended to those who have received appropriate mathematical training and are aspiring to become system theorists.
Another type of simulation that is less intuitive is to perform simulation calculations.
6.2 State space
For a complete view, each system must have a unique location, which is the ultimate meaning of "complete" and "system".
We saw how to decompose "attributes" from the system through segmentation. The product space shows how to put them back together in a systematic way. If each decomposition is a real division, then the product space must include all the original possibilities. In this case, everything should have its place, and everyone should be in its place.
The points on the plane do not represent the state of one system at different times (the so-called "diachronic perspective"), but the states of different systems at the same time ("synchronic perspective"). This method works well for both perspectives and corresponds to the common scientific method of replacing successive observations of one system with multiple individual observations of similar systems, and vice versa.
If we succeed in finding a perspective that makes the system behavior appear continuous, we can think of the arrows pointing from one state to another as very, very small. In this case, we can have the concept of two states being "close", so that the area on the plane can represent a set of states, or an interval related to each other. Topology, one of the branches of mathematics, studies how to transform perspectives while keeping properties such as "closeness" unchanged. But the complexity of mathematics cannot hide the fact that the initial "closeness" is determined by the observer.
The value of this representation lies not in what is on the picture, but in what is not on the picture. While everything should have its place, some places may be empty. That is, some combinations of properties are not observed. These holes in state space remind us: 1. Our observations are not complete, and there are other states that have not yet been observed; 2. Our classification of attributes is too broad.
Ordinary people who are not mathematicians often feel awe when they hear talk about n-dimensional space, and think that mathematicians have super thinking abilities. In fact, mathematicians are special only in their ability to extrapolate. They cannot "see" n-dimensional space and just continue to apply the same mathematical operations regardless of how many dimensions are involved. A point in two-dimensional space is designated by two numbers, and a point in three-dimensional space is designated by three numbers. Therefore, by extrapolation, a "point" in seven-dimensional space is designated by seven numbers. A one-dimensional object (a line segment) splits a two-dimensional object (a plane) into two parts. A two-dimensional object (a plane) splits a three-dimensional object (a solid) into two parts. Therefore, by extrapolation, a six-dimensional object splits a seven-dimensional object into two parts.
When talking about dimensionality reduction, whatever you want to say, please add the words "image of". At least when we say this, we remind ourselves that some information has been discarded and we may wish to recover it.
To recover the information lost due to projection, we must obtain system information from other channels, that is, information about the missing dimensions. This reverse operation can be called expansion, and it is also an important reason why the state space perspective is valuable. We just need to add a dimension to each newly discovered variable. In this way, our past work can be retained, because the past state space becomes a projection of the new state space, so our previous observations are still meaningful explanations.
An empirical rule for behavior in state space, that is, the diachronic rule: If the behavior line crosses from , then either: 1. The system is not determined by state Either: 2. What you see is a projection, an incomplete view.
Synchronicity law: If there are two systems at the same position in the state space at the same time, then it means that the dimension of the space is too low, that is, the view is incomplete.
6.3 Time as a benchmark for behavior
The choice of system properties is a compromise between the convenience of independence and the necessity of completeness.
We propose the Rule of Counting to Three: If you can't think of three ways to abuse a tool, you don't know how to use it. Adherence to this rule protects us from the fanaticism of optimists, exaggerators, and other perfectionists of all kinds, but primarily from ourselves.
Talking about step functions and slow rising curves without knowing the time scale is technical nonsense. Time scale has no absolute meaning, it only has meaning when compared with other time scales.
Paradoxically, one way to solve the problem of too many dimensions is to introduce another dimension, the time dimension. Among all possible dimensions, time has the special property that it always moves in one direction. In other words, time cannot be turned back. Since t will never take on the same value twice, you can completely eliminate loops or any form of crossover, regardless of whether you are pious or resourceful. A cycle is no longer the repetition of the same state, but the experience of similar states at different times. Furthermore, measuring time allows us to distinguish similar cycles that proceed at different rates.
One drawback of the state space representation is that our brains lack visual imagination for spaces higher than two and three dimensions. To make matters worse, two- or three-dimensional space has flaws as a communication medium. Although we can solve n-dimensional problems in our own minds, how do we communicate these problems to others in three-dimensional space?
Science can be seen as a process, that is, exploring the angles from which things can be viewed to produce unchanging laws. Therefore, scientific laws describe how the world looks (I discovered it), or stipulate how to see the world (how I discovered it). We really can't tell the difference between the two.
What the experimenters discovered was that, although the cells in computer memory that store membership levels would change their values, there were always 100 storage cells. From a white box perspective, this law is extremely boring, but from a black box perspective, this is a real discovery.
6.4 Behavior in open systems
Loops are characteristics of system behavior determined by states. If we see that the system forms a loop, we guess that it may not be affected by external factors at present. Of course, it may be affected by external factors of the cycle, or the external factors may be too small to break the cycle.
Why do physics and chemistry laboratories need to build an ideal closed environment? The purpose is to create a system with a certain status for research. Why do they like to study systems with a certain state? Because the behavior of a system with a certain state is simple. Everything that happens in the system can be represented by disjoint lines of behavior.
However, if an observer takes all these issues into account and successfully isolates the system within the walls of perfection, lines of behavior may still tangle, at which point he will say that he sees "randomness." However, observers have no reliable way to distinguish randomness from hidden openness, the "leaky wall."
Observers will introduce differences. He may observe at different times and see different behaviors of the system, so he sees different parts of the behavioral line. Another observer may see different behavior because he defines the system differently, or distinguishes different characteristics, or uses a different time scale. Even the same observer may be "different" at different times, because he can completely change the combining method, dividing method or time scale.
Describing a system in terms of typical behavior and describing a system in terms of unexpected but important behavior are two of the ways we are used to restoring the single line of behavior we like in closed systems.
The teacher decided to describe John's overall behavior in terms of an isolated behavior as a way to simplify the behavior of the open system.
Because of the fear of surprise, we usually observe the system for a period of time before describing its overall behavior.
(Almost) Regardless of the initial state and input sequence, the system will reach the same final state. Such a system is called a "same-final" system. Homogeneous systems are attractive to us because we need consistent behavior and simple descriptions of observations.
Since we can be both observers and environment, we can both predict its behavior and influence its behavior.
6.5 The Law of Uncertainty
Uncertainty Law: We cannot determine whether the observed constraints should be attributed to the system or to the environment.
Chapter 7 Some system issues
Only change is eternal.
7.1 Systematic triarchy
Therefore, the following are three important issues that dominate general systems thinking, that is, the systems triarchy: 1. Why do I see everything I see? 2. Why do things stay the same? 3. Why do things change?
Only then did we ask the question of evolution: "How did things develop to what they are today? Why can't they stay the same forever?"
The real transformation here is from focusing on organizational form to focusing on action, from existence to behavior, from form to function, from pattern to process, from eternity to temporary existence. "Existence" is the intersection of entity and time. Over a period of time, those aspects of organization that seem to be relatively unchanged constitute the basic structure of an entity or organism. Invariance over time helps identify important parts of a mature system. Instead, there are short-lived, reversible changes that occur over time, which often occur repeatedly, and constitute "behavior" or function; those long-term, irreversible changes, which often occur gradually, constitute "evolution" or development . With this passage of time, people's attention to entities has also changed: from objects (patterns of matter in space) to behaviors (patterns of events in time). ——R. W. Gerard
All general systems thinking must start from one of the problems and start exploring until it is forced to switch to another problem. We can never hope to reach the end, nor will we try. Our goal is to improve thinking, not to solve the Sphinx's puzzle.
Where have we traveled? Using Gerald's terminology of "being, doing, evolving," we have discussed ways of recording existence: collections of symbols, structure diagrams, properties, boundaries, and white boxes. We studied behavior: state spaces, timing diagrams, inputs, randomness, and black boxes. We also studied the relationship between existence and behavior: how to infer a specific structure from a specific behavior by extracting "attributes"; how to produce a specific behavior from a specific structure by executing a "program".
But we also look at all of these things from a fourth perspective in particular, which is belief. We ask: How do observers (or believers) participate in these observations? The answer comes in many forms: eye-brain law, generalized thermodynamic law, generalized complementarity law, difference law, invariance law, strong connection law, image law, synchronic and diachronic law, uncertainty law, etc. The conclusion given by all these answers is that we as observers are entangled with the observed phenomena, and this entanglement leads to our ultimate inability to determine what is existence and what is belief.
7.2 Stability
Physicists recognize this problem, so their concept of stability relates to so-called "small perturbations." The system is only slightly open, and then we observe its behavior. If the influence of the disturbance on the system gradually disappears, then the system is stable; conversely, if the effect of the disturbance is amplified, the system is unstable.
Stability not only means the limit of changes that the system can withstand, but also the degree of disturbance that the system can withstand. Therefore, when we refer to stability, we include two meanings: some acceptable behavior of the system and some expected behavior of the environment.
While this argument is sufficient for scientists to study nearly closed systems, for those who cannot avoid openness in the laboratory, it is purely misleading. Specifically, it can misdirect attention, causing us to look for stability “within” the system rather than seeing it as a relationship between the system and its environment. When nature wants to preserve an irreplaceable resource, it won't do anything until people actually destroy the ecosystem. There is no precise definition of "small disturbance" yet.
The concept of linear systems, while beneficial to systems thinking, also pushes absolutism into a more sinister realm. No system we know of is strictly linear.
Circular Argument: The current formulation of scientific aims and methods is based on a cultural idea and this needs to be clarified. If we can isolate more important cultural institutions from their unique circumstances, classify them into categories, and practice until repeated occurrences lead to precursors or functionally related things, then it can be considered that the cultural institutions we examine are fundamental and unchanging, while those things that lead to uniqueness are secondary and changeable.
Human thought, and the science that has sprung from it, can only grasp and name the important side of facts, as their relations, laws, in short, the unchanging parts of eternal change; but not the Materiality, personalization, these aspects pulse with reality and human life, and are therefore fickle and intangible.
Stable = benign? Because: Change means that the old concept system is inappropriate, and it requires a huge amount of energy and energy to reconstruct the concept system. This is a choice that life instinct does not like.
7.3 Survivability
Survival is what really matters to the system. Since persistence is the continued existence of a system, to clearly understand the meaning of persistence, we must examine the meanings of "continuance" and "existence."
Why does the system survive? In the long term, this is because the systems that don't survive are no longer there and we don't think about them. The systems we often see are systems selected from all past systems as the best "survivors."
"Persistence" refers to the period of time that a system must exist for it to be worthy of study.
7.4 Identification
To exist is to have a logo. Logo is actually synonymous with survivability, because if it cannot survive, there is nothing to label, and once something changes its logo, it means it no longer exists.
If we adopt a programmatic approach to identifying similarities and differences, we can clarify the concept of "identity". This field is also known as "pattern recognition" or, more specifically for visual images, "image processing".
"Difference is the most basic concept in cybernetics", and the same is true in general systems thinking. We must always remember that this is also the most difficult concept.
7.5 Adjustment and adaptation
The concepts of "regulatory" and "adaptive" come from two sides of the white box-black box debate, so their clarity depends on how clear the P and V divisions are. But if the logo is changed, the system is not considered "adapting," but rather "no longer surviving."
Within the computer, hardware represents the "laws of nature" and is also the stage where simulation is realized. While the simulation "relies" on this hardware, the key point is the drama, not the stage management.
Law of effect: Small changes in structure often lead to small changes in behavior. Or in our words: Small changes in the white box often lead to small changes in the black box. on the other hand: Small changes in behavior often result from small changes in structure.
We can call these two viewpoints "white box" and "black box", such as: mechanical mechanics and thermodynamics, physiologists and behavioral scientists.
7.6 Old Car Law
He filters out warning signs in his environment and, in our opinion, adopts a regulatory approach as much as possible to avoid adaptive changes in his behavior. However, in his own mind, his adjustment is to maintain his identity and to survive. The more effective this conditioning system is, the less likely he is to change the unpleasant behavior. The only hope for change is to either change the way he identifies himself or drastically increase his suffering.
Old car rule: 1. Systems that regulate well do not require adaptive changes; 2. The system can simplify its conditional work through adaptive changes.
Should old cars be maintained or reconditioned?
Deal with stress or change yourself
1. If the way of looking at the world does not put undue pressure on the observer, there is no need to change. 2. Ways of seeing the world may change to reduce stress on the observer.